Euler's Theorem

Theorem: If  
\[a \in \mathbb{Z}_n^*\]
  then 
\[a^{\phi(n)} = 1 \pmod{n}\]
.
This reduces to Fermat’s Little Theorem when  
\[n\]
  is prime.
Proof: Let  
\[m = \phi(n)\]
, and label the units  
\[u_1,...,u_m\]
. Consider the sequence  
\[a u_1,...,a u_m\]
 (we multiply each unit by  
\[a\]
). If  
\[a u_i = a u_j\]
, then multiplying by  
\[a^{-1}\]
 (which exists since 
\[a\]
 is a unit) shows  
\[u_i = u_j\]
, hence the members of the sequence are distinct. Furthermore products of units must also be units, hence  
\[a u_1, ..., a u_m\]
 must be  
\[u_1,...,u_m\]
 in some order.
Multiplying all the units together gives  
\[ a u_1 ... a u_m = u_1 ... u_m.\]
.
Rearranging yields  
\[ a^{\phi(n)} = a^m = (u_1 ... u_m)(u_1 ... u_m)^{-1} = 1 \]
.
Similarly Euler’s Theorem also gives an alternative way to compute inverses. For  
\[a \in \mathbb{Z}_n^*\]
,  
\[a^{-1}\]
  can be computed as  
\[a^{\phi(n)-1}\]
. This is efficient as we may use repeated squaring, but Euclid’s algorithm is still faster (why?) and does not require one to compute  
\[\phi(n)\]
.
These theorems do not tell us the order of a given unit  
\[a\in\mathbb{Z}_n^*\]
 but they do narrow it down: let  
\[x\]
 be the order of  
\[a\]
. If we know  
\[a^y = 1\]
 by Euclid’s algorithm we can find  
\[m, n\]
 such that  
\[ d = m x + n y \]
.
where  
\[d = \gcd(x, y)\]
. Then  
\[ a^d = a^{m x + n y} = (a^x)^m (a^y)^n = 1 \]

thus sinc e 
\[d \le x\]
 we must have  
\[d = x\]
 (since 
\[x\]
 is the smallest positive integer for which  
\[a^x = 1\]
), and hence  
\[x\]
 must be a divisor of  
\[y\]
. Thus by Euler’s Theorem, the order of  
\[a\]
 divides  
\[\phi(n)\]
.
These statements are in fact trivial corollaries of Lagrange’s Theorem from group theory. Of course Fermat and Euler died long before group theory was discovered.

You have no rights to post comments